Postliberal Order

Postliberal Order

Share this post

Postliberal Order
Postliberal Order
Why Liberalism Can’t Limit Government
Copy link
Facebook
Email
Notes
More

Why Liberalism Can’t Limit Government

A common liberal misconception has distorted the Thomistic view

Patrick J. Deneen's avatar
Patrick J. Deneen
Aug 11, 2022
∙ Paid
50

Share this post

Postliberal Order
Postliberal Order
Why Liberalism Can’t Limit Government
Copy link
Facebook
Email
Notes
More
12
1
Share

An essay appeared today on the website Public Discourse that offered a defense of “limited government” on what was described as “Thomistic” grounds. When such defenses appear on websites such as Public Discourse, Law and Liberty, Acton.org, and the numberless astroturfed right-liberal websites, you can be virtually certain that such arguments deserve one response:

The Postliberal Order is a reader-supported publication. To read this and all posts in their entirety, please consider become in a paid subscriber.

The essay, written by Catholic University philosophy professor Melissa Moschella, was a distillation of “new natural law” arguments developed by John Finnis and Robert George. Another way of describing this project is “Whig Thomism,” the effort to wed the Aristotelian-Thomist philosophical tradition and classical liberalism.

Here is an example of the line of thinking deployed by Moschella to justify “limited government,” and a preference for personal liberty, on “natural law” grounds:

Finally (though this list is not exhaustive), because not all of the basic goods can be pursued to the same degree or at the same time, natural law requires establishing and following a reasonable order of priorities among goods in one’s own life and in the lives of one’s communities, based on personal vocation, organizational mission, and other circumstances. This implies that the freedom and authority to order one’s own pursuits and those of the communities under one’s care are crucial for leading a flourishing life. And it is also why a well-ordered political community is obligated to respect the freedom and authority of individuals and smaller groups to direct their own affairs, an obligation that natural law thinkers sometimes refer to as the principle of subsidiarity.

Note the swift move from endorsing certain “basic goods” essential to human flourishing, to the need to “follow a reasonable order of priorities among goods,” to the heavy lifting suddenly done by what follows from the word “implies”: the “crucial” need for “freedom [to] order one’s own pursuits,” and the “obligation” of a “political community . . . to respect the freedom and authority of individuals and smaller groups to direct their own affairs,” all linked finally to “the principle of subsidiarity.”

The entire paragraph is a non sequitur, in which the entire second half does not follow from the first. Yes, Aquinas acknowledges that requirements of the natural law must admit of prudential application—such as the great difficulty in eliminating prostitution from human societies. But this is a different claim from suggesting that such prudence “implies” that “political communities” are “obligated” to give a place of primacy to the “freedom and authority of individuals to direct their own pursuits” or “affairs.” The political order, rather, is in the first instance obligated to organize itself through law (or through upholding of custom) that rightly directs people toward their ends of flourishing.

Postliberal Order is a reader-supported publication. To continue reading this post, support our work with a paid subscription.

This post is for paid subscribers

Already a paid subscriber? Sign in
© 2025 The Postliberals
Privacy ∙ Terms ∙ Collection notice
Start writingGet the app
Substack is the home for great culture

Share

Copy link
Facebook
Email
Notes
More